Argument
In logic, an argument (Latin argumentum: "proof, evidence, token, subject, contents") is a connected series of statements or propositions, called premises, that are intended to provide support, justification or evidence for the truth of another statement, the conclusion.[1][2]
Cogito ergo sum Logic and rhetoric |
![]() |
Key articles |
General logic |
Bad logic |
v - t - e |
To assess an argument, one must see whether its premises support its conclusion, more specifically, one must see whether the argument is either deductively valid and sound or inductively strong and cogent.[3][4]
Deductive
A deductive argument asserts that the truth of the conclusion is a logical consequence (C) of the premises (P). Deductive arguments are judged by the properties of validity and soundness.[5] An argument is valid if and only if the conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises.A sound argument is a valid argument with true premises.
Validity
In order for an argument to be valid, it has to satisfy the following condition: if the sentences are true, then the conclusion has to be true as well. In order words, an argument is logically valid if it is in principle impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false at the same time. Meaning the premises may be false, but if they weren’t, the conclusion would be true.
Validity is completely determined by an argument’s structure, not its content. If some argument is valid, then every argument with the same structure is also valid.[note 1]
For example:
- P1: All birds can fly.
- P2: Penguins are birds.
- C: Therefore, penguins can fly.
However, we know for a fact that penguins cannot fly. This argument is valid because, assuming the premises are true, the conclusion must be true. However, the first premise is false. All birds do not fly. Birds are scientifically defined as “a group of warm-blooded vertebrates constituting the class Aves, characterized by feathers, toothless beaked jaws, the laying of hard-shelled eggs, a high metabolic rate, a four-chambered heart, and a strong yet lightweight skeleton.”
Invalid arguments involve several fallacies that do not satisfy the requirement that an argument must deduce a conclusion that is logically coherent. A common example is the non sequitur, where the conclusion is completely disconnected from the premises.
Not all fallacious arguments are invalid. In a circular argument, the conclusion actually is a premise, so the argument is trivially valid. It is completely uninformative, however, and doesn't really prove anything.
Soundness
Soundness is related to validity and has the following requirements:
- The argument is valid.
- The argument has true premises.
The following argument is valid and sound.
- P1: All Greeks are human.
- P2: All humans are mortal.
- C: Therefore, all Greeks are mortal.
The above example is based on a simple argument structure, but arguments can have many many premises, which can make debating the soundness of an argument extremely difficult in some cases.
In debate or discourse
In everyday practice an argument may be structured into talking points, issues that are supposed to help support said argument. Talking points based on distorted or false reality are often used in propaganda venues and political debates in tandem with loaded language to sway the course of a debate towards a predetermined conclusion. Such tactics turn an argument into emotional manipulation (having an argument) as opposed to logical exercise (making an argument).[6]
See also
- Logical fallacy
- Not an argument — No it isn't.
Want to read this in another language?
Notes
- For example:
- P1: All basketballs are round.
- P2: The earth is round.
- C: Therefore, the earth is a basketball
- P1: All X are Y.
- P2: Z is Y.
- C: Therefore, Z is X.
- P1: All basketballs are round.
References
- Argument | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosphy
- See the Wikipedia article on Argument.
- Deductive and Inductive Arguments | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosphy
- See the Wikipedia article on Argument § Standard types.
- Validity and Soundness | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Smith and Volk. Having or Making an Argument. Quakers Colonel, 2009.